Skip to content
Snippets Groups Projects
Commit e702347a authored by Dan Licata's avatar Dan Licata
Browse files

response

parent 4052cd7f
No related branches found
No related tags found
No related merge requests found
We thank the reviewers for their very helpful feedback and will revise
the paper accordingly.
1. Reviewer C says "Moreover, the paper doesn't produce any particular
equalities that one might want to reason with while programming."
We would push back on this criticism: we show soundness of an entire
class of equalities that are useful for program reasoning by programmers
and compilers alike: things like lifting an if statement (or more
generally any pattern match) out of a lambda are very common in
refactoring and optimization, and induction is fundamental for any
program verification.
In terms of "actionable" theorems, we show that upcasts form complex
values and downcsats form complex stacks, which also justifies
refactorings and optimizations. For instance, upcasts, as complex
values, can be freely (de)-duplicated, discarded if not used, and lifted
out of loops as if they were values. Downcasts, as complex stacks, are
strict in their input, which aids strictness analysis, as in optimizers
for lazy langauges.
2. Reviewer C asks about the meaning of L514 and whether or not our
syntactic theory of term dynamism and equivalence is not only sound
but *complete* for contextual equivalence.
Our sentence is a bit awkwardly worded, but we mean that if two terms
are equidynamic, then in operational models they should be
contextually equivalent. We do include beta-eta in the definition of
term dynamism in figure 4, where they are labeled as axioms of term
dynamism, but this is not enough to prove completeness for an
effectful language like cbpv: for instance, both sequential and
non-deterministic languages should model all of axioms. To ask if our
syntax is complete for contextual equivalence we need to fix a
particular model. The syntax is not intended to be complete for any
particular model, in order that it apply to as many models as
possible. This is what allows us to interpret the model with
incompatible definitions of the dynamic type and extend it with new
axioms based on that model like those given in figure 5.
3. Reviewer C asks "Do these theorems hold when you distinguish
between different errors via, e.g., blame labels?"
It seems likely, but it's not yet clear how to formalize these properties
with multiple blame labels.
For instance, the dynamic gradual guarantee allows for a more
precisely typed program to error with a blame label different from the
less precise program.
So if our ordering models the dynamic gradual guarantee, this means
that blame(l) would be a least element of our ordering for every label
l so any two blame errors would be equivalent.
On the other hand the uniqueness theorems seem that they should hold
when all of the casts involved have the *same* label; we plan to
explore this in future work, building on
the unpublished tech report:
https://newtraell.cs.uchicago.edu/research/publications/techreports/TR-2004-02
4. Reviewer D asks to clarify lines 116-117.
Yes, we mean that the typed equivalences should hold in the statically
typed portions of the code; the dynamic type casts ensure that the
equivalences hold in statically typed portions of the code even if they
interact with (more) dynamically typed code. We expect that it will be
rare for gradually typed programs to be completely typed (e.g. this is
very rare in Typed Racket).
5. Reviewer D asks about languages where dynamism doesn't go all the
way up to ? if we can still reduce everything to upcasts and
downcasts.
The use of ? in the factorization of a cast A => B can be replaced with
any type D that is more dynamic than both A and B, so ?, if it is
present, always works. We would be curious to know of any systems where
a cast A => B was allowed but they have no common dynamism-supertype.
6. Reviewer C says that we "restrict to non-effectful programs" and
finds it surprising because "blame is an effect".
This is not what we intended by that comment in the intro (which is only
explaining that the eta rule in traditional call-by-value is restricted
to values). In this paper, we do treat dynamic type errors as an effect,
and as Reviewer D notes, this is one of the main reasons we use CBPV: to
have an axiomatic theory that is valid in the presence of arbitrary
effects.
7. Reviewer A asks "(l35) eta is mostly used in one direction for optimization, it's
the other direction that fails for these cases right?"
Yes, in the "eager" cast semantics, the eta law for functions should be
an ordering `V <= \x -> V x` but it's debateable whether this means that
the right should be allowed to be optimized to the left. This would make
the semantics of the program dependent on the precise behvior of the
optimizer, so it would be very hard to change the optimizer without
either making code error that didn't before or vice-versa (because
whether or not an optimization is triggered can be very sensitive to
small changes).
8. Reviewer C comments on some missing related work.
We apologize for the oversight and will add appropriate discussion; for
Henglein, a significant difference is that the equational theory there
is based on a rewriting system with cast rules for each pair of types,
whereas in our approach those rules are a theorem following from the
universal characterization of casts. For others TODO?
9. Reviewer B: we apologize that the presentation was not accessible and
will work to give a better high-level introduction in the revisions.
The reason existing work does not suffice is that gradual typing
introduces a dynamic type ? and type casts, and the question is how
to enrich the equational theories of CBV and CBN with these features.
0% Loading or .
You are about to add 0 people to the discussion. Proceed with caution.
Finish editing this message first!
Please register or to comment