diff --git a/gcbpv.tex b/gcbpv.tex index 1d5593057db7453f430b5f65f1f756fee6e4a00c..e1851743a3286ff12b709198432e12c4e5da9c83 100644 --- a/gcbpv.tex +++ b/gcbpv.tex @@ -1,7 +1,7 @@ \documentclass{article} \usepackage{float} -\usepackage{amsmath,amssymb} +\usepackage{amsmath,amssymb, amsthm} \usepackage{tikz-cd} \usepackage{mathpartir} \usepackage{rotating} @@ -532,10 +532,138 @@ from a preordering. \section{Connectives and Contract Uniqueness Theorems} -Next we consider the multiplicative and additive connectives of -gradual call-by-push value, and their corresponding contracts. +Next we consider the contract uniqueness theorems for the connectives +of call-by-push-value. % -We start with the additives because they are comparatively easier. +First, an abstract perspective on the following theorems. +% +The primitive rules of upcasts and downcasts covariantly assign an +upcast $\upcast {A}{A'}$ to any value type dynamism judgment $A \ltdyn +A'$ and contravariantly assign a downcast $\dncast {\u B}{\u B'}$ to +any computation type dynamism judgment $\u B \ltdyn \u B'$. +% +Next, note that \emph{every} type constructor in call-by-push-value is +jointly functorial in its arguments, with the domain of the function +type being the only contravariant position of any of the connectives +(though if we have EEC connectives, it's more complex). +% +When these two variances align, the contract uniqueness theorem is +very simple. +% +We call any connective where all \emph{covariant} arguments are of the +same \emph{sort} (i.e., value vs computation type) and all +\emph{contravariant} arguments are of the opposite sort a \emph{nice} +connective. +% +Then every nice connective has a nice uniqueness theorem for its +same-sorted cast, i.e., upcasts for value types and downcasts for +computation types. + +The only two connectives in CBPV that are not \emph{nice} are the $\u +F$ and the $U$ types since each are covariant in their argument but +swap sorts. +% +And correspondingly, neither of these types has a fully general +contract uniquness theorem. +% +That is, for a base value type dynamism $X_1 \ltdyn X_2$, we have no +contract uniqueness theorem for the downcast given by $\u F X_1 \ltdyn +\u F X_2$. +% +However, that's not to say that $\u F$ and $U$ have \emph{no} +associated uniqueness principles: instead, we will show in what +follows that the application of $\u F$ or $U$ to any connective can be +shown to have a uniqueness principle. +% +Unlike with functoriality, we do not know the general principle, but +it seems closely related to work on so-called ``direct models'' of +effectful computation, i.e. Freyd Categories, Fuhrmann's Abstract +Kleisli Categories and Munch-Maccagnoni's duploids. + +\begin{theorem}[Admissibility of (Almost All) Downcasts] + Any upcast or downcast associated to a cut-free type dynamism + judgment (i.e., one only built out of monotonicity rules) in gradual + call-by-push-value is equivalent to a term whose only upcasts and + downcasts are those that are ``axiomatically undetermined'': defined in + figure \ref{axiomatically-free}. +\end{theorem} +\begin{proof} + We prove the theorem by induction on dynamism derivations with $4$ + mutually recursive cases + \begin{mathpar} + \inferrule{A \ltdyn A'}{\upcast A {A'}} + \inferrule{A \ltdyn A'}{\dncast{\u F A}{\u F A'}} + \inferrule{\u B \ltdyn \u B'}{\dncast{\u B}{\u B'}} + \inferrule{\u B \ltdyn \u B'}{\upcast{U \u B}{U \u B'}} + \end{mathpar} + The cases are all in other sections, we record them here to state + precisely the inductive structure of the proof and cover the trivial + cases (units). + \begin{enumerate} + \item Value Types + \begin{enumerate} + \item $1 \ltdyn 1$: upcast is identity, by decomposition theorem, + similarly for downcast. + \item $A_1 \times A_2 \ltdyn A_1' \times A_2'$: see multiplicatives and use the inductive hypothesis. + \item $0 \ltdyn 0$: By $\eta$ for $0$, must be $\case x \{ \}$, + similarly the downcast must be equivalent to $\lett x = \bullet; \case x \{ \}$. + \item $A_1 + A_2 \ltdyn A_1' + A_2'$: see additives and use + inductive hypothesis + \item $U \u B \ltdyn U \u B'$: by inductive hypothesis on $\u B + \ltdyn \u B'$, there is an upcast $U \u B \ltdyn U \u B'$. For + the downcast, we need a downcast $\dncast{\u F U \u B}{\u F U \u + B'}$, for which we use the inductive hypothesis for $\u B + \ltdyn \u B'$ and the functoriality of $U, \u F$ (see the + exponential section). + \end{enumerate} + \item Computation Types. + \begin{enumerate} + \item $\top \ltdyn \top$: by $\eta$ for $\top$, the downcast must by $\{\}$. Similarly, the upcast must be $\thunk\{\}$ + \item $\inferrule{A_1 \ltdyn A_1' \and A_2 \ltdyn A_2'}{A_1 \times + A_2 \ltdyn A_1' \times A_2'}$ See additives section and use the + inductive hypotheses + \item $\inferrule{A \ltdyn A' \and \u B \ltdyn \u B'}{A \to \u B + \ltdyn A \to \u B'}$ See multiplicatives section and use the + inductive hypotheses. + \item $\inferrule{A \ltdyn A'}{\u F A \ltdyn \u F A'}$ for the + downcast, use the inductive hypothesis. For the upcast, use the + inductive hypothesis and see the exponential section. + \end{enumerate} + \end{enumerate} +\end{proof} + +\begin{figure} +\begin{mathpar} + 1 \ltdyn \dynv + + \dynv \times \dynv \ltdyn \dynv + + \dynv + \dynv \ltdyn \dynv + + U \dync \ltdyn \dynv\\ + + \dync \wedge \dync \ltdyn \dync + + \dynv \to \dync \ltdyn \dync + + \u F \dynv \ltdyn \dync +\end{mathpar} +\caption{Cut-Free Type Dynamism (with $\dynv, \dync$)} +\end{figure} + +\begin{figure} + \begin{mathpar} + \upcast{T}{\dynv} + + \upcast{U \u M}{U \dync} + + \dncast{\u M}{\dync} + + \dncast{\u F T}{\u F \dynv} + \end{mathpar} + \caption{Axiomatically Undetermined Upcasts, Downcasts} + \label{axiomatically-free} +\end{figure} \subsection{Additive Connectives: Positive Sum, Negative Product}